David Congdon and Use of Heidegger in Bultmann, Barth, Pannenberg
¶ 1
First, I would like to consider the
important role of existentialism as theology considers the nature of humanity. The
issue in the Barth-Bultmann debate is whether Barth was right in saying that
the role of existentialism in Bultmann is similar to that of a full-blown
natural theology. His concern is that such an approach so heightens the
thoughts and observations of human beings that it devalues our reliance upon
revelation for knowledge of God. Congdon will say that Barth is quite wrong,
and I would tend to agree. This debate has led me to re-visit existentialism.
As important as philosophy has been to the history of theology, theology needs
to be sure its engagement is a critical one. I will explore the way Bultmann,
Barth, and Pannenberg make use of Heidegger and see what we can learn of a
proper theological use of a philosophical perspective.
The tie that Bultmann developed
with existentialism was the reason Pannenberg thought Bultmann eclipsed Barth
in the theological world, at least in the 70s and 80s. Barth would likely
concur, since in the early 60s he thought the academic world of theology had
already set him aside. The place of existentialism is far more obvious in
Bultmann than we find it in Barth. In CD III.2, Barth will be in a subtle
conversation-debate with existentialism. On an anecdotal level, I must say that
even in conservative Christian schools I attended, reading Kierkegaard,
Heidegger, Sartre, and Camus was important, even if to argue against, in some
cases, was the primary purpose. Congdon suggests that Bultmann had a far more
modest approach to his use of existentialism than Barth thought. Bultmann would
agree with Barth that a philosophical perspective should not become a worldview.
I will show that we have some different approaches to Heidegger in these
theologians.
Bultmann was a faithful pupil of
Wilhelm Herrmann. One of the things Bultmann learned from him is the exclusive
relation to existence or self of all statements about God and divine action.
Hermann could say that the object of theology is God, but that theology discusses
its object by speaking of the God who confronts human beings in the light of
faith. Faith becomes a matter of comprehending our existence, which is at the
same time comprehending God. If we speak of God, then we must speak of
ourselves. This amounts to saying that statements about God and divine action
bear on human existence. This means the rejection of objective statements about
God that do not bear directly upon human existence. Such objective statements
about God that do not bear upon existence are the realm of myth and
world-picture. This connection to Herrmann is one that Barth noted. He
described it as the ethical and anthropological form that Bultmann gives to the
message and faith of Christianity. Bultmann also derives from Herrmann his holy
respect for the secular rules for the world and science.[1]
In a limited way, Bultmann sought a
point of contact between theology and nontheological anthropological studies. Heidegger
was that point of contact. To view the matter from the perspective of Barth for
a moment, Barth refers to Heidegger as developing a modern ontology instructed
by Kierkegaard. It interprets human existence historically, projecting itself
toward nothingness. He thinks that Bultmann sought to understand human
existence prior to faith along the lines of Heidegger. Bultmann shares the
methodology of Schleiermacher, which means the analysis of human existence
provides the framework of a general view of humanity.[2]
Barth will stress that modernity is not the measure of all things, even while
it appears indispensable. Existentialism will have a successor. The time of the
dominance of Hegel had more justification for the place it gave Hegel than do
persons today have for giving existentialism such a dominant role. He thinks
theology needs to be more far-sighted and reject any attempt to co-ordinate
with this temporarily predominant philosophical trend of existentialism. Yet,
on the positive side, Barth admits that we need to consider and learn from the
typical philosophical thinking of the day.[3]
For Bultmann, one can elaborate existentially the subject matter of theology
only in the form of anthropology. He sees the point of contact as resolving the
opposition of revelation to the human being as sinner. However, he viewed
revelation as a judgment on the negation of the human. Thus, he did not achieve
a critical appropriation of an anthropology based on existential philosophy.
Yet, he regarded this anthropology as normative. He accepted as valid the
pretheological interpretation of the person given in the analysis of human
existence by Heidegger, but without any critical discussion of the individual
claims made in that analysis. He offered a global negative evaluation of it as
a description of the understanding of human existence by the sinner and used it
in this form as a negative foil for theology.[4]
My hope is that the discussion will show how a theologian might engage in a
critical discussion of existentialist analysis.
Let us consider human brokenness
under the theme of the theological understanding of original sin. Barth will
argue that the empirical psychological data had no connection with Christian
theological statements about human sinfulness. When we know Jesus Christ, we
know the sinfulness of humanity.[5]
Yet, this would mean that those who do not believe would have no realization of
the brokenness that characterizes human existence. At the same time, it seems
self-evident that those who have no faith must still face the confrontation
between their human destiny on the one hand and the structure of their behavior
on the other. Thus, one can legitimately make a point of contact between
theology and philosophy as the philosopher might disclose dimensions of human
brokenness. Heidegger could certainly have insight into the nature of that
brokenness. Of course, Barth is partially correct, for the knowledge of God
makes it possible for us to see the perversity of the behavior of sin arising
from a turn from God. Such knowledge arises from a turning in faith to the
self-revelation of God.[6]
If we turn to Pannenberg, we see a
theologian who is going to be willing to re-think the notion of original sin in
light of the exploration into human existence we find in existentialism in
general and Heidegger in particular. He will focus upon the insight that
anxiety or dread is primary as we consider the structure of human existence.
Thus, Kierkegaard is largely correct. He came close to dissolving the
transcendental concept of the subject of idealistic philosophy. The subject is
in a state of becoming with regard to its selfhood and therefore its freedom.
Dread for him has no definite object, other than the one experiencing dread as
a concern for the unity of the self. Dread particularly experiences the loss of
connection with the Infinite, and thus grasp at finite things to bring
wholeness. As the synthesis of the Infinite and the finite, he is describing
the same thing that many thinkers describe as self-transcendence, openness to
the world, and exo-centricity. As finite beings, humanity reaches beyond
finitude and toward the Infinite and Eternal. This reaching out would not be
possible if human beings were simply finite. Theologically, we can think of the
brokenness of the synthesis as a reflection of the dignity of humanity as made
in the image of God and the misery of humanity in its sinfulness. Heidegger
will take the phenomenon of dread or anxiety as a paradigm for the basic
structure of human existence in the world. He will remove anxiety from a
tension between the Infinite and Eternal as seen in Kierkegaard and locate it
fully in the experience of individuals in this world. Care with regard to self
determines the structure of human existence. Self-love becomes the focus of
human existence. As care for self dominates us, our lives no longer have a life
characterized by trust that becomes the basis for behavior. Rather, we strive
for security. A life dominated by such striving for security and control of the
conditions of our existence means self-love rules us. Sin is our ruler. Self-preservation
is normal and natural, but when it proceeds from anxiety and worry, it distorts
our behavior with undue self-love. Heidegger provides confirmation that anxiety
or dread is an expression of sin.[7]
Bultmann will see this as well.[8]
Human brokenness is such that the
process of achieving our personal identity becomes a way of revealing the
brokenness of human existence. In Heidegger, one can achieve identity by
knowing one’s destiny, which one achieves through behavior. One has a certain
kind of indebtedness of existence that we find expressed in being responsible.
Heidegger describes this experience in terms of human beings owing it to
themselves to correspond to this destiny. One is responsible to oneself. To
appropriate this thought critically, responsibility to God is a particular form
of responsibility to the self. After all, the identity of the self, or the
destiny of the self, has its ground in God and one can achieve this destiny
only through the power of God.[9]
We can see Heidegger working on the
achieving of personal identity in the theme that human existence has its
concern for the being that it must be. Human existence is disclosure, for human
existence is being-there in the world and is there for itself. We can
understand this as an explication of the consciousness of human existence of
its own being. As such, Heidegger is correcting the classical philosophical
analysis of self-consciousness. For Heidegger, the future about which human
existence has concern and which it must be is decisive for its being as a
whole. The present being of human existence has its basis in the future with
which it has concern to be. He has introduced the time factor into the analysis
of self-consciousness that yields its meaning only on the basis that the constitution
of human existence is by the future in the whole of its being. As he would put
it, the question of personal selfness is accessible only by anticipating the
future of one’s own death. The “extreme” place that death has in a human life
becomes revelatory way as we “anticipate” that future in all this nothingness. Sartre
would later connect this anticipation with the question of God. The point of
Heidegger is that as long as human existence is as an entity, it will never
reach its wholeness. The gain of its wholeness is the loss of Being-in-the-world.
Heidegger has transformed the important notion of self-transcendence as
transcendence toward nothingness. The only way out of the questionable quality
of human existence is the anticipatory knowledge of the death of the person.
The anticipatory knowledge opens the possibility of the certainty of one’s
Being. The certainty comes specifically through the call of conscience. The
calling is from oneself. Answering the call is the achieving of identity. This
ecstatic being-ahead-of-oneself in the future of the person has a positive
understanding of the present as moment. The present is the moment in which
human existence returns from its future in repetition to its past.[10]
This view of achieving personal
identity has several challenges that deserve critical appraisal. One is the
material abundance of possibilities of life preceding death apart from
knowledge of inescapability of one’s own death. The contingency of events
leading up to death argues against Heidegger here. In addition, death does not
round out human existence into a whole. Death breaks off life. Even in the best
instances, the successful life remains a fragment. We could also say that the
intention toward wholeness necessarily reaches beyond death. The intended
wholeness transcends the finitude of human life. The web of social life is part
of this transcendence. Yet, the reciprocal relation of the social group and the
individual suggests a bond that transcends them both that we might call the
destiny of humanity. Self-transcendence is toward something rather than
nothing. Yet, Heidegger is quite right to point to the importance of
anticipation as the means through which humanity experiences its wholeness.[11]
Let us shift our attention to Barth
in these matters for a moment. If Heidegger should receive commendation for his
introduction of time into human existence, Barth will offer his approach to a
critical appropriation of the insight in his attempt to correct it in light of
revelation. Barth discusses “the time of revelation,” with the first section
becoming a discussion of “God’s time and our time.” To discuss the notion of
God revealing whom God is to discuss the occurrence of an event. This means,
“God has time for us.” Yet, he gladly points out that he shall not have to take
as a basis any time concept gained independently of revelation itself. He
rejects the approach of both Augustine and Heidegger. He refers to Being and Time, Section 65. Temporality
is “original time” and becomes the possibility of existence in virtue of which
one may have anxiety as one lives ecstatically by means of a preliminary resolve
to achieve one’s possibility of existence. One attains oneself by facing a
guilty past and thereby possessing a present. Existence “is” by bringing to
fulfillment of one’s future. Humanity possesses time by creating it. He sees
the problem that if we create time, time might be lost. Time in Heidegger
becomes a self-determined of human existence. Reality lies with this existence,
with temporality as the possibility of existence, but not with time as such. He
will go on to discuss his notion of the time of revelation. Heidegger strips
time of its objectivity in order to regard it as the way in which human beings
exist. We are not sure what we mean by the present, we are not sure if it
begins and ends, and we just wonder if we can say anything of time if we do not
also speak of eternity.[12]
Barth will also have an important
reflection on Nothingness in CD III.3 [50] as he wrestles with evil in creation.
In the process, he discusses the role of Nothingness in Heidegger. He will
offer his critical appraisal of the term. In Heidegger, Nothing is something in
the sense that one has to reckon with it as an original factor that precedes
our negation and affirmation. “Nothing” is dynamic and active. It obtrudes upon
us. It discloses itself to us in dread, which is the nihilating work of “Nothing”
as the rejecting, reprimanding, and elusive being. Dread discloses the
previously hidden alienation of the other. Here is the path toward self-hood
and freedom. Nothing belongs to the essence of being. Existence derives from manifested
nothing. One can define existence as a projection into Nothing. He agrees with
Hegel and that pure being and pure nothing are the same thing. We have
discussed the disclosure that occurs in affective states like joy and boredom.
However, the basic mood that reveals Nothing as constitutive for existence is
dread. The revelation of Nothing occurs in dread. Dread reveals nothing because
we elude ourselves. Dread strikes us dumb. Revelation of Nothing discloses the
strangeness of human existence. Heidegger wants to show the potency of Nothing
against existence. Along with dread, Nothing brings peace and rest. Barth will
make the point, in fact, that Nothingness has the nature and function of deity.
He notes the underived, comprehensive dynamism, and activity of this Nothing.
Openness to Nothing is the virtue of existence. Distortion of Nothing is a sin.
Nothing exhibits the nature and mode of what philosophy would normally refer to
as transcendence. Nothingness in its dominant and dynamic depth takes the place
of deity. Nothing is the divine. Nothing is the basis, criterion, and
elucidation of everything. He notes that while Nothing has traditional
attributes of deity as aseity, uniqueness, omnipotence, omniscience, infinity,
and so on, Nothing has no relation to the biblical concept of God. Of course,
the notion of Nothing in Heidegger, he says, has nothing to do with what he has
considered as nothingness before God. Thus, Nothingness in Heidegger is really
something. Nothing is being that has some dimension of the holy and divine.
Peace, serenity, and daring, overcome the revelation of Nothing in dread.
Nothingness becomes something fruitful, salutary, and radiant rather that
something dreadful and horrible or a dark abyss. In this regard, Nothingness in
Heidegger is nothing like the Nothingness of Christian usage, where the
sickness unto death confronts real nothingness.[13]
Closely related to human brokenness
and the difficulty of achieving personal identity is the questionable character
of human existence. It suggests perpetual openness of humanity to the future.
It suggests the provisional nature of choices and beliefs. For Barth, humanity
itself is a question to which the divine is the answer. Barth (Romans, 41) could say that when the
final human question awakens in us we receive the divine answer. He sees a
correspondence between the question and the divine answer (Romans, 80, 271-2, 380 and The
Word of God and the Word of Man, 191). The value of the Law and the
multiplicity of religions is that they keep the question open (Romans, 254). He stresses the point that
the divine call precedes the question. People call upon God, but God has
already answered (Romans, 383). The
answer to the question that animates human existence is the personal presence
of God. In fact, God has placed us in question precisely because God is the
answer to the question of our existence (Romans,
80, 282). He developed this point further in Christliche Dogmatic (1927) by stressing that humanity is the
question, but that the divine answer discloses the questionable character of
human existence. In fact, the answer awakens the question. Barth will abandon
this mode of thinking in Church
Dogmatics. He had given up on the possibility of claiming human existence
itself as a witness for the truth of revelation. Thus, Barth can say that
religion is a confirmation that sin has not destroyed the relation of humanity
to God (IV.1, 483).[14]
Religion in early dialectical theology is the self-assertion of humanity that
feels its lost condition. In contrast, faith is the human response to the
self-revelation of God. This contrast between faith and religion was a
criticism of the middle class Christian world emerging in Europe. It directed
itself against all forms of religion, including that of Christianity.[15]
Bultmann will stress that the very
existence of humanity already has the character of a question and is in fact
the question of God. Our finitude and self-awareness of it raises the question
of Infinity and our relationship to it. Humanity raises the question about
itself because God has called humanity into question. God is the answer to the
question humanity of itself. He will stress that since humanity is a question
to itself it already knows about God. Philosophy knows about faith in that it
knows the freedom of human existence, which suggests the questionable character
of human existence. Bultmann sees an unobservable, hidden correlation of God
and self. Questionableness is the structure of human existence. The self is in
quest of itself. He affirms a reciprocal relation between our existence and
God. We can know God only as we know self; we can know self only as we know
God. Faith provides moral certainty of God. The self arrives at authenticity
only in God. Of course, one does not objectify any of this. Only science
objectifies the world and the phenomena of the human. Faith allows one to
transcend the observable world. Scripture itself arises out of the quest for
authentic existence and speaks to our quest for the same. Thus, Bultmann
remains faithful to Herrmann in seeing this hidden correlation between God and
self. The emphasis of Karl Barth on the Trinity as the self-revelation of God
gives way in Bultmann to the disclosing of the authenticity of human existence.
In a sense, Bultmann replaces proof of God from nature and history with a proof
of God to the believing self and existing authentically. This dialectic between
human existence and transcendence has replaced the language of religion that
connected soul and God. Its connection with Augustine is that nothing is so
certain that we are aware of our existence and therefore know God. This path to
knowledge of God from knowledge of self continued in Bernard of Clairvaux. Even
John Calvin worked out a dialectic relation between the knowledge of God and
self-knowledge. In criticism of this view, we should not it has a weakness that
it shares with existentialism in general. We arrive at self-knowledge through
participation in the world that science describes.[16]
To be clear, the question contained
in human existence is not the answer, for the answer is only through revelation.
Humanity has knowledge of God in the uncanniness and enigmatic quality of human
existence. The inquiry about God arises from the mystery and finitude of
humanity. The question of the authenticity of human existence is always ahead.
Human life is always provisional. Yet, Bultmann makes it clear that humanity
tries to close the questioning off with a positive knowledge of God, which
turns humanity into a prisoner. Christian faith celebrates the question raised
in the non-Christian, but must point to the answer divine revelation. Here is
the point of contact that Bultmann sees with the existential analysis of human
existence. The alliance that Bultmann sees with existentialism points to his
difference with Barth.[17]
As a brief aside, the method of
correlation in Paul Tillich is close to both Barth and Bultmann. For him, what
is at stake in the effort to interpret the Christian revelation as the answer
to the question of human existence and of finitude generally is the ability of
theological statements to compel conviction. Gerhard Ebeling will take this
further, saying theology establishes the possibility of its talk about God
having the power to compel conviction by explaining it as an answer to the
questionable character of human existence and of reality generally as it
confronts humanity. For Barth and Bultmann, this would be true as well.[18]
We should also note that the
important notion in Bultmann of “pre-understanding” arises from the questioning
character of human existence. The questioning without which we cannot
understand the text is the presupposition of understanding. The questioning
character of the pre-understanding makes room for a revision of any given
pre-conception about the content of a text through a confrontation with the
text. However, Bultmann restricts the question about the contemporary
significance of the past to that which a transmitted text expresses concerning
the question of human existence. This restriction of the text to
anthropocentric understanding of existence seems to deny the challenge that the
past may present to the present. It assumes the present age is self-sufficient.[19]
We have taken a detour into the
importance of humanity as a question. The questionable character of human
existence is the reason personal identity is so difficult. The detour highlights
an important point. One does not achieve identity so easily. A theological
approach may help us consider the place of the existential analysis of human
existence.
Mood discloses the manner of human
existence in the world and discloses it as a whole. Human existence is this
disclosedness. Such disclosure is the openness of human existence to the world.
People often read Heidegger at this point as focusing upon the mood of anxiety
or despair, which leads to isolation of the self from the community. Yet, he
also writes of joy and other positive moods as liberating. Such feelings open
the individual to the community.[20]
The call of conscience is from the person in the mode of keeping silent. The
call is from fallenness into “they” and to its unique potentiality for Being. In
this way, he shifts conscience from the awareness of fault. Rather, guilt
arises from Being with Others and even from relationship to any law or “ought.”
In essence, individuals must bring themselves back from their lostness in
“they.” “Being-guilty” is the expression of an ought, the content of which is
the authenticity of the individual. Guilt as involving a transgression becomes
intelligible in this way. He has recovered the notion of guilt as something we
owe to someone or something. Guilt involves awareness of obligation before it
involves awareness of transgression. Our responsibility for ourselves arises
out of this sense of obligation. This idea is similar to that of Paul Ricoeur (Symbolism of Evil, 102), where he said
that acceptance of responsibility is the basis of the consciousness of being an
agent or author. The concept of action presupposes the concept of
responsibility. Both the capacity for action and the sense of responsibility
have their ground in the call to an authentic self. The judgment of conscience
is a failure concerning achieving one’s self. I become conscious of something I
lack and something I need.
Many of us can appreciate the
insight Heidegger brings to self-revelation we experience in mood and in guilt
in particular. Yet, in the process, engaging Heidegger critically at this
point, Heidegger plays down the consciousness of guilt in the sense of having
already violated an obligation and done a wrong that one cannot undo. His
analysis fails to penetrate the depth of the nonidentity that makes itself
known in awareness of guilt because it fails to see the rupture of communal
order by a rending of the ties individuals have to their fellow human beings.
Had he done so, he would have seen that the authentic self of an individual is
a member of the human order to which it belongs. Had he been aware of this, he
might have seen the importance of expiation (extinguishing the guilt incurred
for the rupture of community, to put an end to the anger or sorrow that results
from this disruption) in overcoming the nonidentity experienced in conscience
that one is to accomplish in the life of the injured community. The result is
that his analysis of conscience leads to an abstraction of the individual from
the human community and its ethos. Heidegger has recognized the subjective form
of the judgments of conscience. Yet, it abstracts conscience from all reference
to the order of the social world. He has also brought into the coming of
consciousness the modern notion of alienation. In fact, the call of conscience
locates consciousness in its isolation. It leads into despair. Theologically,
the notion of repentance opens the door to overcoming the judgment of
conscience and the experience of nonidentity.[21]
A different way of putting this objection is that in Bultmann we find the
reduction of the Christian ethic to the ethical demand to accept one’s self and
take responsibility for the world in general. Such a focus upon the individual
at least seems to quit the realm of justice and the social order. It runs the
risk of becoming socially irrelevant. In addition, describing the church as a
community of faith and a community in the transcendent will not disturb the
official doings of society.[22]
To conclude, I think I have shown
that Bultmann is much less critical in his approach to Heidegger as are Barth
or Pannenberg. Both Barth and Pannenberg engage Heidegger in a critical way.
While Barth wants to distance himself from Heidegger, he has also drawn from
his insights. Pannenberg is allowing existentialism to inform the Christian
notion of sin. Yet, he also makes it clear that the theologian brings Scripture
and tradition into dialogue with its insights. I have not included his
reflections on how he can biblically bring dread and anxiety into an
understanding of the brokenness of humanity. In fact, he will criticize Barth
at this point. Barth has an incredibly insightful discussion of sin as pride,
sloth, and lying in Volume IV. These reflections on sin have strong connections
to Christian tradition. Pannenberg wants to move with Bultmann in
re-considering (demythologizing) the doctrine of original sin as directing us
to the anxiety or dread that is constitutive of human existence.
[1] (Moltmann, Theology of Hope 1965, 1967) , 58-60.
[2] (Barth 2004, 1932-67) Volume I, [2.2] 37;
[6.2], 192-3.
[3] (Barth 2004, 1932-67) , Volume III.3 [50.3]
334.
[4] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
19.
[5] (Barth 2004, 1932-67) , IV.1, p 389.
[6] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
91-2.
[7] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
96-104.
[8] Theology of the New Testament, I, 243-44
on fear in Paul and 241-42 on care.
[9] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
113-4.
[10] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
209-11, 234, 237-9.
[11] (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology (2 Volumes)
1967, 1971) ,
Volume I, 166-7.
[12] (Barth 2004, 1932-67) , Vol. I.2 [14.1]
45-47; 47-9.
[13] (Barth 2004, 1932-67) Volume III.3 [50.3]
334-49.
[14] (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology (2 Volumes)
1967, 1971) ,
Volume II, 207-10.
[15] (Moltmann, The Church in the Power of the Spirit: A
Conribution to Messianic Ecclesiology 1975, 1977) , 154-5.
[16] (Moltmann, Theology of Hope 1965, 1967) , 273-6; (Moltmann, The Crucified God 1973, 1974) , 87-91; (Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom: The Doctrine
of God 1980, 1981) ,
15.
[17] (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology (2 Volumes)
1967, 1971) ,
Volume II, 210-2. He refers to Faith and
Understanding and Essays
Philosophical and Theological. (Moltmann, Theology of Hope 1965, 1967) , 59-65, who also
refers to Kerygma and Myth.
[18] (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology (2 Volumes)
1967, 1971) ,
Volume II, 212-3.
[19] (Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology (2 Volumes)
1967, 1971) ,
Volume I, 107-15.
[20] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
254-6.
[21] (Pannenberg, Anthropology in Theological Perspective
1985) ,
301-3, 308-10.
[22] (Moltmann, Theology of Hope 1965, 1967) , 314-6, 321.
Comments
Post a Comment